Friday, June 26, 2015

The Moral Ambivalence of Instinct

Instinctual behavior is neither moral nor immoral, and society is not obligated to celebrate instinctual behavior.  Instead, political actors and constituencies should focus moral debates (especially the debates surrounding same-sex marriage) on the moral factors external to instinct rather than using minority instinct as a rhetorical bludgeon. 

People on both sides of the same-sex marriage debate sometimes posit that what is natural or instinctual matters.  These proponents of same-sex marriage state that because some people are born instinctively homosexual, that homosexuality is not morally inferior to heterosexuality.  Conversely, some opponents of same-sex marriage will state that same-sex marriage is immoral because homosexual behavior is not natural or is not naturally sustainable.
Both arguments miss the mark.  My disagreement centers on the fact that instinct is morally ambivalent.  Sometimes instinct is helpful; sometimes it is not.  Sometimes an instinct is ethically sound; sometimes, it is not.
In this discussion, I define instinct as a behavior to which one is driven or impelled but which is not required.  Reflexes cannot be controlled, but instincts can.  Generally speaking, these instincts are manifestations of one’s inborn nature but can also be affected by environment and culture.
Sexual orientation, for example, is a manifestation of sexual preference inspired by inborn, environmental, and cultural factors, and which exhibits varying degrees of plasticity.  The debate surrounding same-sex marriage sometimes relies on the specious premise that the expression of a person’s instinct, specifically the portions of his or her sexual orientation which are inborn, is naturally and inevitably an ethical expression of the human experience.
The fact is, however, that instinct has no morality or immorality about it—not one instinct can be lauded as completely good, nor can any instinct be castigated as completely bad.  Take, for example, the maternal instinct.  This is one of humanity’s hardest-of-wired instincts, and for good reason.  Without it, we would probably not survive as a species.  Its impulse, the protection and rearing of children, is unquestionably a social good and its application is profoundly ethical in most circumstances.  However, there are some situations in which it may not be.  Should a woman or man misplace that impulse and want to care for a person other than a dependent child the resulting “parenting” would be tyranny. (I am reminded of several of C.S. Lewis’s hell-bound characters in The Great Divorce).  Additionally, the impulse to care for a child may also be extended past its useful time period, allowing the child to remain in a state of dependency long after it is necessary or desirable.
Other instincts can yield both ethical and unethical applications.  The fight or flight instinct can yield ethical results, such as defending one’s home from a violent invader, or when one flees a dangerous situation.  It can also yield unethical applications, such as when people engage in road rage or when they pick a fight in response to a slight grievance.  The self-preservation instinct can prevent imminent harm from coming to a person, such as when one is looking over a cliff or dropping sharp knives.  It can also yield unethical applications, such as when one overreacts and cause great harm to another.  Greed can help provide for one’s family, but it can also unethically take from others.  The instinctive pull most feel toward fat, sugar, and salt can give us much needed and rare nutrients.  It can also cause obesity and a host of other health problems when such nutrients are not rare.
Sexual orientation is similar, in that some applications of it are moral and some are not.  Sometimes we are driven to use the sex act for good and beautiful purposes; sometimes, people are driven to use the sex act for selfish, violent, or depraved purposes.  Our job as moral agents is not to “find” ourselves by discovering the behaviors to which we are most driven, but to conduct an ethical calculus and then rationally choose which behaviors we should carry out. 
The whole point is that our behavioral instincts are, in and of themselves, neither good nor bad, and that the locus of ethical decision-making takes place outside of instinct itself.  As a result, such arguments as “I’m built this way, so how can it be wrong?” or “It’s not natural!” don’t hold any water.  Instinct, one way or the other, has nothing to do with morality. 
Instead, morality stands apart from instinct simply because it is so completely rational.  Instinctual behavior is the behavior to which we are driven; it doesn’t require much thought, except perhaps in its fulfillment.  We don’t often question why or whether we should eat, or sleep, or mate; we only wonder how and when.
Ethics, however, are rational.  When thinking about ethics and morality, we’re thinking about something that is purely theoretical.  To be certain, we often think about practical applications of ethics in our daily lives, but the heart of the matter itself—what is right and wrong—inescapably demands that we think in theoretical terms.
Additionally, ethics and ethical laws are external to the self.  When we judge our actions as moral or immoral, we are not looking inward to determine if such actions are in line with a poorly defined most-natural-self; instead, we look outward to determine if our actions are in line with an externally created law of behavior that would exist even if we did not.
If we considered instinctual behavior to be moral and good, we would essentially be making the claim that only the Self matters.  Such a wholesale acceptance of instinctual behavior would not only imply the most horrible types of moral relativism, but it would also prohibit moral progression.  If instinct were moral, then not only would it be morally acceptable to do anything one feels driven to do, but we would never become better than we currently are.  We would, quite literally, be damned by our own lusts.
Most advocates of same-sex marriage who use the homosexual instinct argument are not actually claiming that all instinct is good—such a claim is obviously false.  Instead, they make the essentially identical claim that no moral judgment can be made about instinctual behavior.  According to such a line of reasoning, the instinctual behavior of one cannot be inferior to the instinctual behavior of another. Since each person’s intrinsic value to society is equal, and each person should be respected, each person’s nature is equally valuable as well and no reason exists to put one person’s instinct above another.
There are a number of problems with this line of reasoning.  First, it equates ethical reasoning (and the resultant public policy) with instinct, saying that marriage is only the recognition of one couple’s drive to mate, rather than a reasoned attempt to define a society’s institutional incentives toward ethical behavior.  Second, by forbidding moral judgment, advocates of same-sex marriage seem intent to avoid morality altogether.  If instinct cannot be judged, or if society cannot make judgments about which instincts it incentivizes and which it does not, then what can ethics be used for?  What is the use of ethics, if not to make us better than what we are naturally?
After all, the whole point of civilization itself is to change our natures, to get us away from the Neanderthal’s cave and towards a reasoned existence as rational creatures.  Every part of civilization exists to take us away from the type of existence that Hobbes’ Leviathan reminds us would be “solitary, poor, nasty, brutish, and short” and towards a holy city where there are no poor, nor any manner of “ites,” among us.
For decades, however, our society has glibly accepted that we should instead seek to be our most natural (or instinctual) selves.  People leave for foreign locales to “find” themselves.  We created and then glorified teenagehood, a life-stage marked by slavish devotion to hormones and the questioning of moral authority.  This wholesale acceptance of the instinctual, not only as  good or moral but also as inevitable is also behind the sexual revolution and the recent debates surrounding same-sex marriage.
However, because the premise of moral instinct is faulty, such an argument is faulty with it.  As a result, though American political tradition rightly requires us to tolerate LGBT lifestyle choices among consenting adults, we are not morally required to accept, celebrate, or incentivize such choices simply because some are instinctually drawn to such behavior.
The difference between toleration and acceptance here becomes relevant.  We, as a liberal democracy, have among us a diverse group of opinions regarding what is right and wrong.  Part of the challenge of a successful democracy is tolerating the voices and opinions that disagree vociferously with our own.  Those who hold differing opinions from the majority are welcome to express such opinions both as loudly as they wish and in what manner they see fit, so long as they do not harm others or take away others’ rights.
What makes this toleration even more complex is that there are many ways that people voice their opinions.  Sometimes that voice comes in the form of speech; sometimes, it’s a whole lifestyle.  As a liberal democracy, we must tolerate not only speech such as internet comments or blog posts, but also lifestyles which directly contradict our own ideas of morality, providing that such lifestyles do not harm other people in ways that society agrees are intolerable.
Hence, while some may correctly argue that a homosexual lifestyle potentially harms children by denying the child daily access to both a mother and a father, because society considers this a tolerable harm (as evinced by no-fault divorce laws) such harms cannot prevent homosexual or other LGBT lifestyle choices from being illegal.  In other words, because of our society’s pluralistic nature, we must tolerate LGBT lifestyle choices.
This toleration, however, does not require us to accept such a lifestyle as correct or as morally equal to heterosexual monogamy, nor does a tolerant society have to celebrate or incentivize every minority lifestyle it tolerates.  Instead, a tolerant society can very well incentivize the lifestyles it wishes to laud while tolerating, but not supporting or accepting, others.  The decision as to which lifestyles to incentivize and which to merely tolerate can only come after such a society seriously debates the moral status of the lifestyles in question.
In American society, however, the debate to determine whether or not LGBT lifestyle choices are moral has been suppressed.  Rather than encouraging debate, many proponents of same-sex marriage would have us glibly accept the premise that instinctual homosexuality is good and/or inevitable and have us forgo making moral judgments about LGBT lifestyles entirely (which, in reality, is just making inverse moral judgments).
Real debate about the moral foundation of homosexuality and LGBT lifestyle choices has never seriously been entertained in mainstream America, partly because, like all the most important debates, it would be uncomfortable.  Some people would be forced to face intelligently-voiced opinions with which they disagree vociferously.  That’s difficult, even in a mature democracy such as ours.
A real debate about such moral questions will also unavoidably involve questions about faith, both religious and secular.  For those intent on eliminating religious faith from the public square (and on disguising secular faith as “reason”) such a debate would be counter-productive.
That is why the Church and faithful LDS thinkers, as well as our allies in the pro-family camp, are so important.  Rather than acquiesce to the premise of moral or inevitable instinct, we have the opportunity to bring the debate to the correct footing by publically questioning the ethical ramifications of LGBT lifestyle choices.  Some of the questions we might ask include:
·         Is it ethically sound to charge a mentally ill person large sums of money to mutilate their genitalia and then tell them they’ve changed genders?  Can one ever change genders?
·         Is it ethically sound to put young children who feel they are transsexual on hormone medication in an effort to dampen their unwanted gender?
·         If same-sex marriage is morally sound because it is instinctual and because it is conducted among consenting adults, are there no sexual behaviors among consenting adults that are immoral?  Are consent and adulthood the only borders of ethical sexuality?  If so, is teenage sexuality moral?

These questions are simply the start of what our society needs to begin asking itself.  Such questions need to occur in a larger moral debate about the philosophical footing of LGBT lifestyles.  This may only be brought about when LDS and like-minded thinkers start questioning the morality of other people’s instinctual behavior.  As followers of Christ, we have a duty to not judge other people; however, in order to be moral agents we must judge behaviors, whether or not people are instinctually drawn to them.

Saturday, December 21, 2013

Judicial Tyranny and the Slow Cultural Murder of Utah



Utahns are now dhimmi.  Google that word to see what I mean.

I used to be a Utahn, and still am at heart, so to read that Utahn culture and politics are no longer defined by Utahns unsettled me.  I’ll be honest: it frightens me and makes me feel helpless. 

If Utah, of all places, can have a single federal judge wipe out the views of a supermajority of the state’s populace, and institute gay marriage in Utah because he doesn’t see any “rational” reason against it, what is to come?

We don’t have any states rights any more.  Nowadays, the states are more like super-sized counties. 

No longer can we say that Texas and California are different but equally valuable to the United States; no longer can we say that Utah and Oregon have different cultures but similar principles of liberty guiding them.

Now, all the states have to be alike.  Now every culture, every state, every person has to pay homage to the LBGT political agenda.  To publically disagree with them will get you fired from your job at A&E, and now will mean that you no longer have any say in your state’s political and cultural institutions.  Now, activist judges are effectively forcing every state to reward homosexual behavior.

That’s what the fight about the definition of marriage is about: the LBGT political agenda wants to see everyone forced to not only tolerate homosexual unions, but to accept them.  They not only want to have their gay pride parades, but want to force everyone to walk in them. 

I don’t believe this has to be.  The nature of pluralistic society demands that we tolerate homosexuality: if two consenting adults want to have a perverted relationship, that’s up to them.  I DO NOT support or condone any form of persecution against anyone for their lifestyle choices.

That being said, no one has the right to have their lifestyle choices accepted by the government.  No one has the right to be rewarded for loving whichever way they want to. 

What does this mean to Utah?  It means that Utah’s politics and culture are forever in the hands of the federal government.  Now Utah has to reward and incentivize behavior that Utahns feel is immoral.  The changes in these social institutions will in turn change Utahn culture, making Utah into something that Utah is not. 

I’m fine with Utah changing, of course.  Utah needs to change (especially Utahn drivers) with the years.  However, it should be Utahns driving that change.  Eventually, if Utahns want to accept homosexuality, they should do it of their own free will.  A basic tenant of our democratic system is that the majority rules.  This, evidently, is no longer the case.  Now, a supermajority of voters doesn’t matter.  Only one judge’s opinion of what is “rational” is important.  Add some liberal lackeys willing to keep the courthouse open past normal hours and WHAM!! You’ve got instant social change. 

I said that I felt helpless.  This is because voting is obviously no longer effective.  Let me say that again:  IF YOU DEPEND ON THE BALLOT BOX TO GET THIS CHANGED, YOU WILL FAIL.

There are things we can do, however.  We can agitate.  We can demonstrate.  We can engage in civil disobedience. 

Ghandi called it “satyagraha.”  Martin Luther King was a fan, and now I’m suggesting it to you.  I call it NOVA:

No
Obedience
Violence or
Acceptance

No obedience to the rulings of an out-of-state judge:  Because the Constitution does not specifically say that we must accept homosexuality, the judge’s opinion is worth the same as any voter’s. 

No violence against anyone because of their political views or lifestyle choices: We are engaging in true political discourse and defining our own society’s social institutions.  Not only would violence be counterproductive, but more importantly, it would be immoral. 

No acceptance of homosexuality: We do not have to think like perverts in order to be good Americans.  We do not have to agree with all other Americans in order to be good Americans.  We can respectfully agree to disagree, let other states do their thing, and do our own thing.

Protest, engage in sit-ins, march, MAKE LOUD NOISES BECAUSE OTHERWISE NO ONE IS GOING TO LISTEN TO YOU.

Unfortunately, I’m not in Utah anymore.  I’m across the country and don’t have the means to get back and agitate.  If I were in Happy Valley, I’d be going door to door by now trying to make it Disturbed Valley.  It would be a tremendous amount of work: there are a couple of political nerds like me, but by and large Utahns are pretty passive.

That won’t work anymore.  Utahns cannot sit on their laurels and depend on their natural cheerfulness and pleasantness to get the job done.  If Utah truly wants to preserve the traditional definition of marriage, Utahns will have to upset some people.  May I suggest that a sit-in in the Salt Lake County Clerk’s office would be the proper first step. 

This will go through the court system for some months.  I hope the Supreme Court will do the right thing and rule in favor of Utahns’ right to define Utahn social institutions.  But what if they don’t?  What will Utah do if the Supreme Court invents new rights that the Constitution doesn’t acknowledge? 

I suggest that Utah simply ignores them, like they should simply ignore this wacko judge.  Let them make whatever rulings they want, UNTIL THE CONSTITUTION  ACTUALLY SAYS SO, WE DON’T HAVE TO ACCEPT GAY MARRIAGE.

That’s my opinion, and my opinion isn’t important anymore, since I moved away from Utah over a year ago.  Evidently, however, Utahns’ opinions don’t matter anymore, anyway.

Like I said: Utahns are now dhimmi.